Can admissible labelling contain Undec(Undecided) argument? - artificial-intelligence

My question is about argumentation theory, admissible sets or labelling.
We define: Label is admissible iff every In labeled argument is legally In and every Out labeled element us legally Out.
My question rises in this point: If labeled set contains Undec argument, is the labelling admissible or not? Is there always exist an admissible labelling of arguments?

Here is answer for my own question:
The empty set of arguments is always admissible.
By definition, it is conflict-free, and since it contains no argument, it cannot be attacked, and therefore trivially defends itself. Therefore, it is admissible.

Related

How expressive can we be with arrays in Z3(Py)? An example

My first question is whether I can express the following formula in Z3Py:
Exists i::Integer s.t. (0<=i<|arr|) & (avg(arr)+t<arr[i])
This means: whether there is a position i::0<i<|arr| in the array whose value a[i] is greater than the average of the array avg(arr) plus a given threshold t.
I know this kind of expressions can be queried in Dafny and (since Dafny uses Z3 below) I guess this can be done in Z3Py.
My second question is: how expressive is the decidable fragment involving arrays in Z3?
I read this paper on how the full theory of arrays is not decidable (http://theory.stanford.edu/~arbrad/papers/arrays.pdf), but only a concrete fragment, the array property fragment.
Is there any interesting paper/tutorial on what can and cannot be done with arrays+quantifiers+functions in Z3?
You found the best paper to read regarding reasoning with Array's, so I doubt there's a better resource or a tutorial out there for you.
I think the sequence logic (not yet officially supported by SMTLib, but z3 supports it), is the right logic to use for reasoning about these sorts of problems, see: https://microsoft.github.io/z3guide/docs/theories/Sequences/
Having said that, most properties about arrays/sequences of "arbitrary size" require inductive proofs. This is because most interesting functions on them are essentially recursive (or iterative), and induction is the only way to prove properties for such programs. While SMT solvers improved significantly regarding support for recursive definitions and induction, they still don't perform anywhere near well compared to a traditional theorem prover. (This is, of course, to be expected.)
I'd recommend looking at the sequence logic, and playing around with recursive definitions. You might get some mileage out of that, though don't expect proofs for anything that require induction, especially if the inductive-hypothesis needs some clever invariant to be specified.
Note that if you know the length of your array concretely (i.e., 10, 15, or some other hopefully not too large a number), then it's best to allocate the elements symbolically yourself, and not use arrays/sequences at all. (And you can repeat your proof for lenghts 0, 1, 2, .. upto some fixed number.) But if you want proofs that work for arbitrary lengths, your best bet is to use sequences in z3, not arrays; with all the caveats I mentioned above.

`nextafter` and `nexttoward`: why this particular interface?

What exactly is the reason behind this peculiar interface of nextafter (and nexttoward) functions? We specify the direction by specifying the value we want to move toward.
At the first sight it feels as if something non-obvious is hidden behind this idea. In my (naive) opinion the first choice for such functions would be something like a pair of single-parameter functions nextafter(a)/nextbefore(a). The next choice would be a two-parameter function nextafter(a, dir) in which the direction dir is specified explicitly (-1 and +1, some standard enum, etc.).
But instead we have to specify a value we want to move toward. Hence a number of questions
(A vague one). There might be some clever idea or idiomatic pattern that is so valuable that it influenced this choice of interface in these standard functions. Is there?
What if decide to just blindly use -DBL_MAX and +DBL_MAX as the second argument for nextafter to specify the negative and positive direction respectively. Are there any pitfalls in doing so?
(A refinement of 2). If I know for sure that b is [slightly] greater than a, is there any reason to prefer nextafter(a, b) over nextafter(a, DBL_MAX)? E.g. is there a chance of better performance for nextafter(a, b) version?
Is nextafter generally a heavy operation? I know that it is implementation-dependent. But, again, assuming an implementation that is based in IEEE 754 representations, is it fairly "difficult" to find the adjacent floating-point value?
With IEEE-754 binary floating point representations, if both arguments of nextafter are finite and the two arguments are not equal, then the result can be computed by either adding one to or subtracting one from the representation of the number reinterpreted as an unsigned integer [Note 1]. The (slight) complexity results from correctly dealing with the corner cases which do not meet those preconditions, but in general you'll find that it is extremely fast.
Aside from NaNs, the only thing that matters about the second argument is whether it is greater than, less than, or equal to the first argument.
The interface basically provides additional clarity for the corner case results, but it is also sometimes useful. In particular, the usage nextafter(x, 0), which truncates regardless of sign, is often convenient. You can also take advantage of the fact that nextafter(x, x); is x to clamp the result at an arbitrary value.
The difference between nextafter and nexttowards is that the latter allows you to use the larger dynamic range of long double; again, that helps with certain corner cases.
Strictly speaking, if the first argument is a zero of some sign and the other argument is a valid non-zero number of the opposite sign, then the argument needs to have its sign bit flipped before the increment. But it seemed too much legalese to add that to the list, and it is still hardly a complicated transform.

Show a language is infinite

Given a DFA M with n states defined over an alphabet ∑, and a string x∈L(M) such that |x|>n, I must show that the L(M) is an infinite language.
Is there any way I can prove this using the pumping lemma?
I'm not immediately sure why the pumping lemma needs to be involved directly. The proof idea is the same one behind the proof of the pumping lemma, and we can explain the relationship. Possibly, with that explanation in hand, you can figure out a way to work out a proof that relies on the pumping lemma directly. I think that should in theory be possible to do without too much mental gymnastics.
Imagine a DFA with three states that accepts a string of length four. This is a concrete instance of the general claim you've been asked to prove. If we can understand why this is specifically true here, it will be easier to generalize to DFAs with an arbitrary number of states.
A DFA executes one transition for every symbol of input. Each transition takes the DFA to some state. Since the string of length four is accepted, we execute four transitions - beginning with the initial state - and we end up in some accepting state. Since each transition takes the DFA to some state, we move into states four times. Since there are only three states in the DFA, that means one of the states was transitioned into more than once: we cannot transition four times around three states without visiting some state more than once. The general principle here is referred to as the Pigeonhole principle: if there are n pigeons in m holes, and n > m, then some hole has more than one pigeon. This is the same reasoning behind why the pumping lemma works, by the way.
Now, consider what this observation means. We accepted a string and, while accepting that string, some state was visited twice. This means that there is a loop in our DFA somewhere - a way to get to an earlier state from a later state - and, furthermore, it is possible to accept strings after taking the loop. If the loop can be taken once:
it might not have been taken at all, so there is definitely a shorter string accepted by the DFA.
it might be taken twice, so there is definitely a longer string accepted by the DFA.
indeed, it might be taken over and over again an arbitrary number of times, so infinitely many longer strings must be in the language.
When using the pumping lemma, you typically assume a language is regular and conclude that what the pumping lemma says about regular languages - what we have said above - is true. Then, you provide a counterexample - a string of length greater than the pumping length p (more on what p is in a moment) - and conclude the assumption is false, that is, that the language is not regular.
The pumping length is essentially the number of states in some DFA for the language. If the language is regular, there are infinitely many DFAs that accept it. For the purposes of using the pumping lemma, it doesn't really matter which DFA for the language you use, since any DFA will visit some state more than once if it processes an input whose length exceeds the number of states in the DFA. Perhaps it is typical to imagine a minimal DFA for the language, which is guaranteed to exist and be unique up to isomorphism.

Difference between symbolic differentiation and automatic differentiation?

I just cannot seem to understand the difference. For me it looks like both just go through an expression and apply the chain rule.. What am I missing?
There are 3 popular methods to calculate the derivative:
Numerical differentiation
Symbolic differentiation
Automatic differentiation
Numerical differentiation relies on the definition of the derivative: , where you put a very small h and evaluate function in two places. This is the most basic formula and on practice people use other formulas which give smaller estimation error. This way of calculating a derivative is suitable mostly if you do not know your function and can only sample it. Also it requires a lot of computation for a high-dim function.
Symbolic differentiation manipulates mathematical expressions. If you ever used matlab or mathematica, then you saw something like this
Here for every math expression they know the derivative and use various rules (product rule, chain rule) to calculate the resulting derivative. Then they simplify the end expression to obtain the resulting expression.
Automatic differentiation manipulates blocks of computer programs. A differentiator has the rules for taking the derivative of each element of a program (when you define any op in core TF, you need to register a gradient for this op). It also uses chain rule to break complex expressions into simpler ones. Here is a good example how it works in real TF programs with some explanation.
You might think that Automatic differentiation is the same as Symbolic differentiation (in one place they operate on math expression, in another on computer programs). And yes, they are sometimes very similar. But for control flow statements (`if, while, loops) the results can be very different:
symbolic differentiation leads to inefficient code (unless carefully
done) and faces the difficulty of converting a computer program into a
single expression
It is a common claim, that automatic differentiation and symbolic differentiation are different. However, this is not true. Forward mode automatic differentiation and symbolic differentiation are in fact equivalent. Please see this paper.
In short, they both apply the chain rule from the input variables to the output variables of an expression graph. It is often said, that symbolic differentiation operates on mathematical expressions and automatic differentiation on computer programs. In the end, they are actually both represented as expression graphs.
On the other hand, automatic differentiation also provides more modes. For instance, when applying the chain rule from output variables to input variables then this is called reverse mode automatic differentiation.
"For me it looks like both just go through an expression and apply the chain rule. What am I missing?"
What you're missing is that AD works with numerical values, while symbolic differentiation works with symbols which represent those values. Let's look at simple example to flesh this out.
Suppose I want to compute the derivative of the expression y = x^2.
If I were doing symbolic differentiation, I would start with the symbol x, and I would square it to get y = x^2, and then I would use the chain rule to know that the dervivate dy/dx = 2x. Now, if I want the derivative for x=5, I can plug that into my expression, and get the derivative. But since I have the expression for the derivative, I can plug in any value of x and compute the derivative without having to repeat the chain rule computations.
If I were doing automatic differentiation, I would start with the value x = 5, and then compute y = 5^2 = 25, and compute the derivative as dy/dx = 2*5 = 10. I would have computed the value and the derivative. However, I know nothing about the value of the derivative at x=4. I would have to repeat the process with x=4 to get the derivative at x=4.

Matlab: assert(array) vs if (array)

In Matlab (as of 2016a) the conditional
if (array_of_logicals) is functionally equivalent to if (all(array_of_logicals)). The documentation says: "An expression is true when its result is nonempty and contains only nonzero elements (logical or real numeric)."
On the other hand, assert() only accepts a "Condition to assert, specified as a valid MATLAB expression." Experimentally, this means an array_of_logicals should be used as assert(all(array_of_logicals)).
What would you say is the reason for the slightly different behavior?
I understand that one reason could be that with assert() you want to exclude the interpretation ambiguity of assert(all(array_of_logicals)) vs assert(any(array_of_logicals)),
but the same could be said about if.
Edit: In particular, I would like to understand, why this behavior was chosen for if.
The purpose of assert is to perform execution tests, so it is reasonable to have coded it to expect a true / false input (i.e. a "logical scalar") representing the test outcome, rather than any nonzero array. The if can afford to be more general, since it's far more likely to receive matrix comparison expressions rather than execution / validation tests.
However, to be honest, I suspect there's no insightful genius behind the decision. The two probably just happened to be implemented independently and the decision was made based on context.
The if behaviour is not new, it has been like this as far back as I can remember. On my 2013a: The statements are executed if the real part of the expression has all non-zero elements. Whereas for assert it just says: evaluate EXPRESSION and, if it is false...
Interestingly, octave did not chose to implement assert the same way. In octave, this test will pass: assert([1,1]==[1,1]);
If you're using assert within your code, you want to make absolutely certain that a given condition is true and part of that is to remove any ambiguity in the definition of true. By requiring a logical scalar, assert forces the user to determine exactly what they expect. This also ensures that if for some reason MATLAB wanted to change how they convert arbitrary data to a logical scalar, your assert calls would remain unaffected.
As far as why if doesn't require an explicit logical scalar, I'm not sure but it's likely just to ease coding, particularly when MATLAB uses the double datatype by default
condition = 1
% This will fail since condition is a double not a logical value
assert(condition)
% This won't work if you required explicit logical scalars
if condition
end

Resources